Ethical Review of Social Sciences
Durham & Thunmann, 2025. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license.
https://doi.org/10.70150/2654b605.
THE MACHIAVELLIAN CHALLENGE TO BUSINESS ETHICS
GEORGE BRAGUES*
Abstract:
No political philosopher is better known in the business world than
Niccolo Machiavelli. His fame resting on The Prince, the
Renaissance Italian writer has often been featured in the popular
business press, mostly to show the relevance of his realpolitik
world-view to the sorts of issues that a contemporary manager is
apt to face. However, the popular view of Machiavelli as a hard-
headed thinker has been challenged by scholars pointing to his
advocacy of republics in the Discourses on Livy, his other great
work. Interpreted along these lines, Machiavelli can be invoked to
support participatory structures in business along with the
cultivation of publicly spirited virtues. We argue that the common
perceptions of Machiavelli are actually on a better track. His
analysis of republics uncovers weaknesses germane to business
that render The Prince more suitable to commercial life. As such,
Machiavelli’s overriding point is that in a competitive arena, such
as that of modern-day business, individuals holding leadership
positions, or aspiring to them, must be prepared to go beyond
conventional morality and live by a different and, indeed, icy set of
rules. Being good in business, Machiavelli warns, will only lead to
personal ruin.
Machiavelli goes further than this, calling for a trans-valuation of
values, wherein the praiseworthy quality of leaders are redefined
so as to take into account the competitive realities of business. In
this new ethic, virtue is connected to acquisitiveness, moral
flexibility, image management, and reaches its culmination in the
entrepreneurial task of founding a great company.
Keywords: Machiavelli, Leadership, Virtue, Vice, Image
Management, Entrepreneurship
JEL Codes: A12, A13, B10, B31, M00, M10, M12, M13, M14
Introduction
To the extent that businesspersons currently look to
philosophers at all for guidance on their affairs, none
is regarded more highly than Niccolo Machiavelli.
Conduct an online search for books on Machiavelli
and business and one will find numerous books with
the Italian thinker’s name cited in the title, ranging
from general handbooks like Machiavelli on
Leadership: Why Machiavelli’s Rules are as Timely
and Important Today as Five Centuries Ago (Ledeen,
1999), Machiavelli on Management: Playing and
Winning the Corporate Power Game (Griffin, 1991)
to works geared to more specific audiences, whether
marketers, Machiavelli, Marketing and Management
(Harris, 2000) or women, The Princessa: Machiavelli
for Women (Ruben, 1988) and Machiavelli for Women
(Smith, 2022). While at times, as in What Would
Machiavelli Do: The Ends Justify the Meanness
(Bing, 2002), the reader is presented with the
caricature of Machiavelli as an unabashed amoralist,
the popular business literature does not revive the
initial estimation of the Renaissance Italian thinker,
which prevailed for centuries after his death, that saw
him as a teacher of evil. Indeed, Alistair McAlpine
somehow manages to infer the point that, “a leader
must be trustworthy” (1998, p. 3), that he or she must
be “unscrupulously fair” (ibid.), and “always resist the
temptation to exchange old friends for new, no matter
how attractive these friendships may appear” (p. 4).
Still, as corroborated in an analysis of Machiavellian
business manuals (Galie & Bopst, 2006), the advice
offered tends to echo widespread understandings of
Machiavellianism that is, as a philosophy that
checks idealist impulses by recognizing the
competitiveness of human existence and enjoining the
necessity of morally questionable tactics in the pursuit
of one’s goals. This conception of Machiavelli’s
thought is also common in the scholarly literature, as
described by Maity et al (2023) through a bibliometric
analysis of existing studies. Nowhere in Machiavelli’s
corpus is the reader more susceptible to being morally
startled than The Prince (1985), a how-to guide for
rulers published posthumously in 1532. It is the work
that is typically referenced whenever the attempt is
made to apply Machiavelli to business.
Machiavelli did, however, write other books. These
include The Art of War, History of Florence, and even
poetry and plays, the most recognized of these being
the comedy Mandragola. Beyond The Prince, his
most important political work is the Discourses on the
First Ten Books of Titius Livius (henceforth, referred
*
Associate Vice-Provost, University of Guelph-
Humber, Toronto, Canada.
george.bragues@guelphhumber.ca.
2
to as the Discourses), in which Machiavelli uses the
ancient historian’s account of Rome’s development as
the background for his own analysis of republican
government. Reading these books, particularly the
Discourses (1970), one meets with a different
Machiavelli than that conveyed in The Prince,
someone more animated by public spiritedness and
moral seriousness. Indeed, the forcefulness of this
figure in the over-all frame of his corpus is such that
it has become fashionable among scholars in the
history of ideas and political philosophy to view
Machiavelli as a champion of classical republican
ideals of liberty, participatory democracy, and
devotion to the common good, the latter exemplified
in the individual practice of the civic virtues (Pocock,
1975; Skinner, 2000). In this interpretation,
Machiavelli is situated within a tradition that goes
back to Aristotle and Cicero and forward to James
Harrington, Robert Sidney, and the civic humanism
that allegedly informed the American founding. This
view has arguably supplanted an earlier opinion, one
which had served to overthrow the old-fashioned
conception of Machiavelli as advocating vice, that
depicted him as foreshadowing Max Weber’s
conception of social science as a value free analyst of
the means necessary to achieve the ends politicians
happen to choose (Olschki, 1945).
1
Modern-day
proponents of Machiavelli’s significance to commerce
could theoretically invoke this approach by
substituting the ends of businesspersons for those of
politicians. Still, their recommendations would still be
compelled to acknowledge the moral dubiety of the
means that Machiavelli proposes. By contrast, anyone
holding to the now more favored republican view
would face a challenge in making Machiavelli
relevant to business. Thus, it has been argued that his
thought cannot properly be applied to business where
the predominant motives of pecuniary self-interest
necessarily collide with the self-denying imperatives
of republicanism (Ramsey, 2000, p. 159). Others
sympathetic to the republican interpretation of
Machiavelli insist that any application of his thought
to business must take into account his condemnation
of the corrupt mores that plagued the governance of
Renaissance Italy, which would translate today into a
concern with corporate corruption (Galie & Bopst,
2006; Cousins & Reina, 2016).
Is the latest academic current on the mark or do the
Machiavellian business primers do a better job of
gauging the Italian thinker? Unsophisticated as the
latter often are, the popular literature at least has the
virtue of faintly grasping that Machiavelli is up to
something dodgy that fundamentally defies the norms
of traditional morality. Nothing about Machiavelli’s
republican leanings rules this out, as I shall argue
1
For an overview of the many interpretations that have been offered
of Machiavelli, see Berlin (1972)
below. My contention is that the analysis of republics
in the Discourses underlines the relevance of the hard-
headed counsel offered in The Prince to the running
of a business. What the leadership gurus, however, fail
to perceive is that Machiavelli is not merely insisting
that a competitive arena like business demands that
those in leadership positions, as well as those aspiring
to them, be prepared to transcend orthodox moral
dictates and operate by a more icy set of rules. I
maintain that Machiavelli’s purpose is much grander
his thought points to a trans-valuation of values,
wherein the virtues and vices of leaders are redefined
so as to take into account the competitive realities of
business. This new value system -- amenable to the
ambitious in business but antithetical to the socially
conscious mindset encouraged in contemporary
business ethics -- comes down to the following advice:
Adopt a general strategy of doing good, as
conventionally defined, combined with a willingness
to depart from that course whenever necessity and
interest requires it, while making sure to rationalize
these deviations to onlookers by framing one’s actions
within a compelling narrative.
1. Republics Vs. Principalities
The Prince begins with the assertion that all
governments have either been republics or
principalities. For us living in the 21
st
century,
accustomed to differentiating between democracies
and authoritarian regimes of one kind or another,
Machiavelli’s dichotomy does not strike us as
unusual. But to someone in his time, it would have
appeared odd because the time-honored typology,
going back to Aristotle’s (1984) The Politics,
organized regimes into three kinds to wit,
monarchies in which authority was exercised by one
individual, aristocracies in which the few ruled, and
democracies where the many held sway (1279a22-
1279b10). In cases which the ruling element pursued
its own interests rather than the common good,
monarchy was understood to have turned into a
tyrannical regime, aristocracies became oligarchies,
and democracies transformed into anarchic mob-rule.
In the Discourses, Machiavelli acknowledges this
categorization, but he insinuates that the gulf between
the good and bad trio is significantly less than his
philosophic predecessors recognized (D.i.2, pp. 106-
109).
2
His reasoning is as follows: history shows that the
first governments were led by single individuals.
Though originally selected for their wisdom and
justice, these monarchs eventually gave way to
hereditary governments. Presumably, this was
2
Henceforth, references to the Discourses will be designated by the
letter, “D”, followed by the book and chapter headings, and then the page
numbers specific to the translation selected.
3
because rulers naturally favored their offspring and
because it rendered more certain who would be the
successor, thereby reducing destabilizing power
struggles upon the death of the leader. But among the
heirs of a monarch, there would invariably be those
that lacked the skills and integrity of the founding
sovereign. As these lower calibre successors would
abuse their power to indulge their every whim, the
elite classes were prompted to stir up and join forces
with the populace in bringing down the tyrannical
order. Consequently, the elites were seen as liberators
and the general public assented to be ruled by them.
This gave rise to aristocracies that initially promoted
the public interest, with memories still fresh of the
oppression suffered during the period of one-person
rule. As time passed, however, and the proceeding
generations took helm of the aristocracy, this ruling
group also succumbed to greed and overweening
ambition. Not having had any direct experience of the
damage caused when leaders put their own interests
above those of the community, they became oligarchs
and went about exploiting the common people. The
populace, in turn, rebelled against the oligarchs and set
up a democracy which, again, served to promote the
common good while the generation that created it was
still alive. Yet once that generation passed, the
democratic regime degenerated into individual licence
and widespread disrespect for authority. The chaos
and lawlessness that ensued drove people to look to a
single individual to restore order and stability. In this
way, we are brought back full circle to a monarchy and
the cycle starts again and continues ad infinitum,
unless something beyond the three basic frameworks
can be established. From Machiavelli’s standpoint,
therefore, the empirical record indicates that sticking
to the Aristotelian typology would pose a mental block
to the design of lasting forms of governance.
Machiavelli espies his alternative scheme in the
historical experiences of Sparta and Rome. If the
former did it by design of its legendary founder,
Lycurgus, and the latter achieved it through an
evolutionary process, both republics wisely mixed
elements of all three of Aristotle’s regimes (D.i.2, pp.
109-111). Sparta reflected monarchy with its two
kings, the aristocracy through its Senate, the
Gerousia, and democracy via its ephors. Likewise,
Rome had its dual consuls as its component of
monarchy, the Senate as its aristocracy, and the
Tribune of the Plebeians as its democracy. By having
all three in the same political order, the excesses of
each were checked and balanced, precluding any of
the sectional interests these embodied from
dominating the laws and policies of the state, and
forcing them to accommodate their legitimate
concerns. With no party capable of lording it over
anybody else, no one was ground down into an
oppressed status where they had little to lose by
subverting the entire political system. This is why,
Machiavelli claims, Sparta endured for over eight
centuries and Rome survived as a republic for
approximately 450 years.
A republic, then, is defined by Machiavelli as a
regime in which authority is shared amongst the
various constituencies in society. Its opposite is a
regime in which authority is not shared, but resides in
a single individual, namely, a principality. Despite
one-person rule being vulnerable to tyranny,
Machiavelli considered principalities an alternative
worthy of consideration because those had proven
capable of forming the basis of enduring order. If we
restate Machiavelli’s classification of regimes in
business terms, a principality would be equivalent to a
sole proprietorship or a corporation in which all the
significant decisions are made by the CEO or more
precisely, an autocratic CEO. A republic would be
analogous to a partnership, assuming the various
partners are equally involved in decision-making. Or,
it could be equivalent to a corporation in which the
CEO (the monarch) depends on the counsel and
support of other top executives along with the heads
of functional or operating units (the aristocratic elite),
and the CEO is closely monitored by the Boards of
Directors along with the leading shareholders (also,
the aristocratic elite), with employees and ordinary
shareholders (the demos) also having some notable
influence on the firm’s affairs. This is not too far from
prevailing conceptions of good corporate governance
as well as the recommendations offered by advocates
of a more participatory culture within companies.
With respect to politics, there can be little doubt that
Machiavelli favors republics over principalities. The
most obvious sign of this is that a principality, being
dominated by the monarchical element, is not so
disposed to embody the checks and balances that
Machiavelli praises. He studied the Romans because
the ancients offered better political models than his
contemporaries, and what especially attracted him to
the past was the greater devotion to liberty then
displayed. It was no coincidence for Machiavelli that
the ancient world also contained more republics than
the contemporaneous political scene. “The study of
history reveals”, Machiavelli says, “the harm that
servitude has done to peoples and to cities” (D. ii. 2,
p. 274). Where individuals are deprived of liberty,
they have less incentive to marry and procreate,
dissuaded as they are by the prospect that their
children might be taken away from them and put into
slavery. Nor can they be so certain that their offspring
will have an opportunity to rise in social position.
Moreover, economic productivity is adversely
impacted by the absence of liberty, since people
cannot be sure of keeping the fruits of their labor and
investment which, by the way, goes against the
thesis cited above that Machiavelli saw commercial
self-interest as necessarily at odds with a well-
constituted republic (D.II.2, p. 280; Ramsey, 2000).
He explicitly concedes that principalities, as opposed
to republics, cannot maintain the people’s freedom
4
(D.i.6, p. 156).
His preference for republics also comes to light in a
revolutionary discussion comparing the political
judgment of princes to that of the public. Before
Machiavelli, political philosophers and historians
were generally sceptical of conferring political
authority on the populace because it was thought that
they are readily swayed by momentary and erratic
passions. The people, so it went, could not summon
the wisdom to manage political affairs properly. This
view is expressed in Plato’s The Republic, where the
ideal regime put forward is rule by a philosophic elite
(1968: 473c-e). Even the more democratic Aristotle
(1984) argued that the best order, in theory at least, is
one in which one or a few virtuous individuals govern
without hindrance (1284a3-11 & 1284b25-34). He
only settled for a mixed regime as a practical
compromise. Let us not forget either that Cicero’s
(1991) devotion to the Roman Republic was based on
the notion that the aristocratic part reflected in the
Senate ought to be predominant over the populace (pp.
78-79). Machiavelli contests this, first, by insisting
that the ancient thinkers put too much stress on the
matter of who is at the helm, rather than the
institutional constraints in which the ruling element is
required to operate. Where institutions buttress the
rule of law, princes and the people are equally
salutary, in that both are constrained from acting
chaotically on their emotional biases (D.i.58, pp. 252-
254).
Indeed, when both are unshackled from the rule of
law, principalities are the more dangerous regime. A
raucous populace can be calmed by a judicious person,
but a vicious prince must be dealt with by eliminating
them from power. And when both the prince and
people are free to wreak havoc, the latter at least have
a better intention: “The brutalities of the masses are
directed against those whom they suspect of
conspiring against the common good; the brutalities of
a prince against those whom he suspects of conspiring
against his own good” (D.i.58, p. 257). In the case
where both are bound by laws, the people again
emerge as the superior option, for they are actually
wiser than princes in making better predictions about
the outcomes of alternative policies. “Not without
good reason is the voice of the populace likened to that
of God” (D.i.58, p. 255). In a debate, Machiavelli
remarks, the public almost always sides with the
sounder position and, in elections, it generally selects
the best candidates. By Machiavelli’s estimation,
there were only four elections that the Roman public
could legitimately regret the votes it cast over the four
and a half century period of the republic. As to why
the public is a more accurate prognosticator than a
single individual, Machiavelli unfortunately says too
little, though he does allude to the fact that a prince is
more apt to be biased by stronger passion. What he
means, one may surmise, is that the populace
assimilates a much wider diversity of emotions than
an individual, so that it is more difficult for a particular
feeling to dominate in skewing a judgement. In this
way, Machiavelli can be said to have foreshadowed
the wisdom of crowds thesis (Surowiecki, 2004).
Beyond that, however, the Machiavellian brief for
republicanism is of limited applicability to business.
The liberty which republics foster may indeed be
conducive to population growth, but the main
beneficiary of that is the political community, whether
by increasing the pool from which to draw an army for
self-defence, augmenting productive factors, or
assuring there are enough young people to finance a
publicly funded old-age pension scheme. It is less
clear how much a firm gains from encouraging its
employees to raise children, for while family
responsibilities might spur individuals to work harder
and more conscientiously, they also could draw
loyalty away from the company. Though a free society
certainly helps businesses prosper, the ideal of liberty
poses a tension to the way firms are internally
organized as hierarchies in which people agree to take
direction from others (Coase, 1937).
More significantly, Machiavelli argues that one-
person rule works best when an existing government
needs to be fundamentally reformed or when a new
regime is being founded. The business parallel to this
would involve an autocrat-CEO in corporate
turnaround situations or during the early, more
entrepreneurial, stages of a company’s development.
Machiavelli’s reasoning here is that any organization
will have narrow interests benefiting from the status
quo who cannot be persuaded to acquiesce to change
on any reasonable terms. Such interests can only be
overcome by a resolute individual willing to use
coercive measures. In this connection, Machiavelli
praises Cleomenes for successfully reforming Sparta
by first killing all the ephors and everyone else who
stood in his way (D.i.9, pp. 133-134). Since firms are
accountable to the laws of a larger community,
Machiavelli would obviously not advise a
restructuring CEO to commit murder, though he
would recommend that those inextricably tied to the
old order be somehow made to leave. Start-ups also
face vested interests, that is, the existing firms whose
business will be negatively impacted should the new
enterprise flourish. Were this formidable opposition to
be managed by a sizable group in which every aspect
of strategy had to be discussed, the inevitable
differences in opinion would hinder agreement (D.i.9,
p.132). A single entrepreneurial CEO can act more
decisively.
The possibility is left that Machiavelli’s
republicanism still serves as a model for healthy and
established companies. Favoring this is Machiavelli’s
claim that republics are more conducive to expansion
than principalities (D.ii.2, p. 275). By having a greater
say in the community’s affairs, the public more
eagerly assumes the sacrifices involved in enlarging
the state’s boundaries. Similarly, in business, if a
5
corporation wants to increase market share, enter new
markets, and introduce new products, it needs the
support of middle-managers, employees, and ordinary
shareholders. They are all more apt to “buy in” to the
company’s growth plans if outlets are available to
express their voices. That said, one must still wrestle
with Machiavelli’s contention that republics should
imitate Rome in making provisions allowing for the
appointment of a dictator for a limited term.
Machiavelli extols this practice: “of Rome’s various
institutions this is one that deserves to be considered
and ranked among those to which the greatness of
Rome’s vast empire was due” (D.i.34, p. 195). What
made dictatorship so necessary was that the Roman
Republic’s growing influence in Italy caught the
attention of neighbouring governments and led them
to join forces against it. In other words, dictatorship
helped Rome manage the challenge of heightened
political competition.
Do Machiavellian principles equally mandate the
practice of dictatorship for companies dealing with
economic competition? Nobody can doubt that
competition between states can impact a larger
amount of people and descend into violence in a way
that intra-firm rivalry does not. Still, though not giving
rise to wars and tectonic shifts in geopolitics, the
casualty rate for companies engaged in market
competition is notably higher than it is for states
enmeshed in international conflict. Not a single
company remains as a component of the Dow Jones
Industrial Average from the beginnings of that index
in 1896, with General Electric being the last original
member until it was dropped in 2018 (Phillips, 2018).
Looking back to the Fortune 500 list in 1955, only
fifty-one companies, about 10% of the original group,
were still in the 2020 rankings (Perry, 2020).
Meanwhile, among the leading states in 1955, only the
Soviet Union has disappeared, while Germany has
returned to its pre-World War II boundaries.
Considering that states have a coercive apparatus at
their disposal to ensure the allegiance of its citizens,
whereas companies are limited to persuading
customers to support its products and services, the
relative permanence of governmental institutions is
understandable. Yet if the political arena was
sufficiently competitive for Machiavelli to advocate
provisional dictatorships, the more precarious rivalry
witnessed in the economic realm makes it all the more
necessary to accept an autocratic office in the running
of companies. As Machiavelli points out, such an
office is compatible with a republican structure, so
long as the autocrat is selected by representative
bodies for a limited term and a specific purpose
(D.i.34, pp. 194-195). Are these not the terms of
modern-day CEO’s? Do they not essentially assume a
temporary dictatorship over the firm for the purposes
3
From here forward, citations from The Prince will be designated by
the letter “P”, then the chapter, followed by the page number specific to
the translation used.
of maximizing shareholder value, doing so by
appointment of the Board of Directors acting for the
shareholders?
2. Virtú and Acquisitiveness
Thus we are brought back to The Prince, where the
popular business literature on Machiavelli has focused
all along. More so in a new venture, but still
significantly so with established companies operating
in a competitive space, a princely authority must take
command. How an individual acquires and maintains
this power is the overriding theme of the first half of
The Prince. It turns out, however, that the individual
who masters this subject is not simply the possessor of
a valuable method, skill set, or technique, the optimal
use of which poses moral questions. In Machiavellli’s
eyes, the maestro of power is nothing less than the
pinnacle of virtue. This stunning claim becomes
evident in following Machiavelli’s use of the word,
“virtú”, Italian for virtue, a word for which translators
have usually substituted, “skill”, or “ability”, and
sometimes, “courage”, “valor”, “strength of purpose”,
or “manliness”. While the last four are somewhat
more positively evaluative than the first two, they still
fall short of what the term “virtue” would designate,
insofar as ordinary conversation occasionally
associates them with morally despicable characters, as
when someone notes that Osama Bin Laden had
strength of purpose or insists that terrorists display
courage. The reason, one suspects, that virtú has
almost always not been consistently rendered into its
English equivalent, virtue Mansfield’s (1985)
translation being the exception is that the
implications of doing so are so morally startling.
In the broadest sense, as Machiavelli outlines, a
person can obtain sole authority either by inheriting it
or without the advantage of family connections.
Clearly, the first instance, what Machiavelli calls a
hereditary principality, is what takes place in family
businesses, which to this day still make up a
significant proportion of the world’s firms (EY
Global, 2023; Conway Centre, 2024). Machiavelli
observes that maintaining power in hereditary
situations is relatively simple because those serving
under the new head are accustomed to the family’s
authority (P.ii, pp. 6-7).
3
All this individual needs to
succeed is a modicum of talent and a willingness to
uphold the company’s traditions. Not having much in
the way of opposition to deal with, the newly minted
boss is not forced to upset anyone. The assumption of
a family business thus poses few moral dilemmas. At
the same time, with Machiavelli making no reference
to virtue at this stage of his analysis, it is apparently
not a role either by which one can express any
6
estimable traits.
It must be admitted that Machiavelli’s reflections
run counter to the well-known fact that family-run
enterprises have an unusually high casualty rate once
the founder has left the scene. Only about 30-40% of
US family-owned businesses survive through the next
generation, and just 10-15% make it to the third
(Beckhard and Dyer, 1983; Applegate, 1994 as cited
in Finch, 2005; Smith Family, 2024). In Machiavelli’s
defence, this might be the consequence of heirs failing
to heed his advice to retain the traditional modes of
operating and being liable instead of implementing
sweeping change in order to put their imprint on the
operation (Miller, Steier, & Le Breton-Miller, 2003,
pp. 521-523). But it might also reflect the
obsolescence of the old ways, the necessity of greater
than average skill at the top of a business, in addition
to the vulnerability of a family business to poor
succession planning and conflict between kin about
strategy. Far from being a calm moral sea, these
battles can render family businesses into ethical
minefields. Successfully navigating these will also
demand more than ordinary virtues, contrary to what
Machiavelli suggests.
Of non-hereditary principalities, Machiavelli
distinguishes four types: mixed, civil, new, and
wholly new. Where someone is already prince, but
then adds to their power by conquering another
already existing state, we have what Machiavelli calls
a mixed principality (P.iii, pp. 7-16). The business
equivalent here is obvious: a take-over. Especially
since the merger and acquisitions wave of the late
1980’s, and continuing more recently with the
ascendance of private equity, take-overs have come
under an ethical cloud because of the painful
restructuring that acquirers typically undertake,
shedding the targets’ underperforming operations,
eliminating jobs, in the process harming the local
community (Di Norcia, 1988; Morgenson & Rosner,
2023). Always the realist, Machiavelli is well-aware
that some will have to be hurt for, “it is a natural and
ordinary necessity that one must always offend
those over whom he becomes a new prince” (P.iii, p.
8). Addressing himself entirely to the self-interest of
princes, Machiavelli counsels them not to hesitate
whatsoever in eliminating anyone standing in the way
of transforming their new possession into a viable
entity.
Machiavelli’s discussion highlights another oft-
cited problem with mergers and acquisitions, namely
that the synergies aimed at often go unrealized
because of a cultural clash between the two firms
(Buono, Bowditch, & Lewis, 1985; Weber &
Camerer, 2003; Goksoy, 2019). Machiavelli alludes to
this in noting that a prince’s difficulties with a new
territory are always greater to the extent one confronts
different customs and language (P.iii, pp. 9-11). Not
surprisingly, he does not even remotely touch the idea
that this cultural divergence is best managed by
promoting dialogue between members of the two
original entities in the hopes of removing invidious
stereotypes, identifying common ground, and
generating mutual respect for outstanding differences.
Implied instead are two more hard-nosed approaches,
with either the CEO maintaining a regular presence at
the headquarters of the acquired company or setting
up a corporate version of a colony. Where the CEO is
onsite regularly, any disruptive activity can be dealt
with quickly, rather than festering to the point where
one can only temporize with it. If staff members want
to enter into the CEO’s good graces, they will
appreciate having easy access to see him or her; and if
they are not inclined to ingratiate the CEO, there will
be greater cause for fear, precisely because the boss is
within striking distance. The flaw in this method,
though, is that the CEO runs the risk of neglecting
matters at the home base. Aware of how this dilemma
can manifest itself in the political area, Machiavelli
prefers the colonization strategy. In the business
realm, this can be accomplished by the CEO
substituting a number of key people from the previous
management team with a group loyal to one’s self.
While those displaced surely suffer, their numbers are
relatively small and, with their no longer being on the
scene, they cannot readily join forces against the CEO.
Meanwhile, the people that were not forced out of the
company will be glad to still have a position and will
tread carefully lest the same fate that befell their old
colleagues strikes them. Cultivating fear is the
Machiavellian way to manage integration risk. It is
also the way leading to virtue, for it is in the chapter
on mixed principalities that the word virtú first makes
it appearance in a descriptive context. Thus, the
Romans are praised for their virtú, in part for their use
of the colonization tactic to assimilate alien territories
into its empire (P.iii, pp. 11-13).
From hereditary and mixed principalities,
Machiavelli turns his attention to new principalities.
Here, rather than appending the new to the old, an
outsider takes control of an established principality.
This is what happens, say, when a new CEO is brought
in to run Bank of America but comes from Goldman
Sachs. According to Machiavelli, the incoming leader
will either face a situation in which individuals are
accustomed to having freedom or lacking it. Again, to
apply this to the world of commerce, the new CEO
might be heading to a firm where power was
previously decentralized, the organizational structure
was relatively flat, and employees were not closely
monitored and instead given latitude to follow their
own paths. On the contrary, the incoming CEO can be
walking into a situation where power had been highly
centralized, a hierarchical order-taking environment
prevailed, and employees were tightly supervised and
expected to meet stringent performance standards. A
company with staff habituated to an autocratic style of
management will, Machiavelli suggests, present little
opposition to a newly appointed CEO (P.v, pp. 20-21).
7
The latter merely need to remove anyone closely
associated with the former CEO so that employees
will not have someone else to rally around.
The difficulties are far greater if the workforce is
used to permissive and consultative managers. To
counter this, Machiavelli suggests the already cited
tack of making one’s presence felt in the company.
The princely CEO should not be aloof or allow
themselves to become isolated, and nor eagerly
delegate tasks to others. They ought to involve
themselves in every aspect of the business to signal
that nothing is done without their sanction. Another
option, Machiavelli states, is for the prince to allow
the people to direct themselves, co-opting a few of
them to forge a loyal governing elite, while ensuring a
tribute is paid. Translating this into business, a CEO
could proceed similarly by leaving the employees’
freedoms and prerogatives untouched, promoting
some ambitious individuals from outside the top rungs
of the organization, and then giving this fresh elite
profit targets to meet. Owing their position to the
CEO, their loyalty will be assured and, because they
come from within the company, their authority is more
likely to be accepted by their colleagues.
However, in further reflecting upon this relatively
benign approach, Machiavelli insists upon the greater
wisdom of destroying the free state: “whoever
becomes patron of a city used to living free and does
not destroy it, should expect to be destroyed by it; for
it always has as a refuge in rebellion the name of
liberty and its own ancient orders which are never
forgotten” (ibid.). The Spartans, Machiavelli
observes, tried setting up oligarchic elites when they
took over the republics of Athens and Thebes, but
failed. The virtuous Romans, by contrast, famously
destroyed Carthage and succeeded in holding it. One
shudders to think how this advice might be put into
business practice, but the reference to Carthage, razed
to the ground by the Roman General Scipio Africanus,
does not mean that a Machiavellian CEO has to wipe
out the company’s offices and facilities. The profit
imperative of business clearly rules out the destruction
of physical capital. It is the firm’s human capital with
which one must deal. With Machiavelli indicating that
a prince must assure, “the inhabitants are broken up or
disbursed” (P.v, p. 21) the CEO intent on following
the Italian thinker will have to literally “clean house”,
by firing the more dispensable employees, or,
particularly if they are essential to the operation,
reassigning them within a revamped organizational
structure so that old bonds and alliances are broken. In
this reorganization, the princely CEO would also be
well-advised to eradicate all vestiges of the old
participatory structures. The number of committees
must be pared down, their membership restricted, their
jurisdiction narrowed.
This anti-democratic counsel is reversed when
Machiavelli addresses civil principalities, understood
as a regime in which a citizen rises to become prince
of his own community (P. ix, pp. 38-42). In business,
this would correspond to the circumstance where the
incoming CEO is promoted from within the
organization. For Machiavelli, the overriding issue
here for the prince is whether they ought to found their
support upon the great or upon the people stated in
business terms, whether to rely on the top executives,
large shareholders, the board of directors or,
alternatively, upon the rank and file employees and, if
it is a large publicly traded corporation, the many
small shareholders. Machiavelli recommends building
on the latter, since the popular element is easier to
satisfy. The elite are ambitious and are willing to take
advantage of employees, say by working them hard to
impress superiors, as well as ordinary shareholders by,
for example, arranging lavish pay packets. Ordinary
workers and shareholders merely desire not to be
exploited by the company’s elites. The ambitions of
the elites are hard to quench without creating hostility
in the rank and file, at which point one is unable to
count on the latter should adversity strike the
company. That, in turn, renders the CEO vulnerable to
the machinations of elites aiming to replace him. By
contrast, a CEO can readily gain the support of those
at the middle to lower rungs of the organizational chart
by preventing their exploitation. Should the CEO
inspire the employees and shareholders as well, both
productivity and the stock price will rise, leaving him
or her virtually impregnable. Indeed, the ideal way to
accomplish this, Machiavelli insinuates, is to initially
gain the leadership role with support of the elites (P.ix,
p. 40). Then, once one has assumed office, one shifts
allegiances to the popular element, which, having
expected the incoming CEO to ingratiate the upper
ranks, will be especially thankful that the new leader
is looking out for their interests. In this manner, the
CEO can harness the people’s energies to motor the
company’s growth, capturing a benefit of the
republican framework without actually having to be
constrained within it (D.i.16, p. 156).
Machiavelli’s examination of the various
principalities reaches its summit in Chapter VI of The
Prince. The subject is wholly new principalities, in
which it is not simply that the prince is new, but the
regime itself has only recently come into being. In
politics, this is the founding of a nation. In business, it
represents the start of a company. Nothing is more
daunting, Machiavelli says, than instituting new
modes and orders, for the founder has enemies in all
those that benefit from the status quo (P.vi, pp. 23-24).
The founders’ base of support is lukewarm at best, for
those standing to benefit from a regime change fear
the repercussions of resisting the old order. Then, too,
there is the innate conservatism of human beings to
overcome, that tendency to be sceptical of anything
beyond the range of one’s experience. Entrepreneurs
face similar challenges, having to deal with
competitors who would rather quash an upstart, rather
than let it grow to the point where it can seize
8
dominance of the marketplace. Banks and investors,
too, are wary of providing financing, as are friends and
family to which the budding entrepreneur often
resorts. To staff the new venture, one usually finds that
the most promising individuals already work at other
companies, from which one must woo them, while
assuaging their qualms of leaving behind a decent
position and potentially rupturing established business
relationships. Not only that, customers wonder how
the young company’s good or service fulfills a need
they never imagined or how it could possibly be better
than the competing firm to which they have long been
loyal.
Given the long odds, Machiavelli argues that the
success of founders cannot possibly be owing to
fortune or luck, except in being afforded an
opportunity. Their success must principally be due to
virtue. Accordingly, Machiavelli summons, “the
greatest examples”: Moses, Cyrus, Theseus, and
Romulus, respectively, the founders of Israel, Persia,
Athens, and Rome (P.vi, p. 22). Were we to come up
with an analogous list of great business founders, it
would have to include John D. Rockefeller, Henry
Ford, Sam Walton, Bill Gates, Steve Jobs, and Elon
Musk. Through their “excellent virtue” (P.vi, p. 23),
they not only serve as role models, but illuminate why
the more common forms of acquiring and maintaining
power lend themselves to the expression of human
excellence, even if a paler version of that manifest in
founding a new polity. In successfully integrating an
acquisition or improving the profitability of an old
sleepy firm, a CEO imitates part of the skill set
possessed by a legendary business founder. On the
Machiavellian view, the exalted virtue of this figure is
like a sun that shines on the performance of lesser
business leaders.
All this begs the question why founding is the font
of virtue, especially insofar as the lustre of that activity
is conceived as dignifying the numerous instances of
morally dubious power plays outlined thus far.
Machiavelli never systematically defends the
superiority of founding. His reasons are scattered
throughout his writings. To begin with, he notes that
seeking resources is natural to human beings. “And
truly it is a very natural and ordinary thing to desire to
acquire” (P. iii, p. 14). The founder takes this impulse
to extraordinary heights by giving birth to something
heretofore not seen. Machiavelli completes that last
quoted sentence as follows: “and always, when men
do it who can, they will be praised or not blamed; but
when they cannot, and want to do it anyway, here lie
the error and the blame” (P.iii, pp. 14-15).
Recognizing how acquisitiveness is ingrained in the
human psyche, public opinion will not begrudge a
person who builds a fortune and, indeed, will admire
them if they do so under difficult circumstances. But
public opinion, Machiavelli claims, is not so
forbearing when someone tries and fails. Every moral
lapse and character weakness is then highlighted,
while the similar failings of a successful acquirer are
overlooked and even the illustrious class of founders,
Machiavelli implies, are impelled by the
precariousness of beginnings to cut moral corners (P.
xvii, p. 66). Like it or not, people judge things by the
outcome: “let a prince win and maintain his state: the
means will always be judged honorable, and will be
praised by everyone” (P.xvii, p. 71). To this,
Machiavelli adds that originators of religions and
states are in fact held in the highest esteem (D. i.10, p.
134). Though not put on the same pedestal, the
memory of those who erected great businesses is
preserved in our day. To be sure, all this assumes that
human opinion is the measure of virtue, instead of
God, nature, or reason. And Machiavelli does, in fact,
hold that morality is humanly constructed. He adopts
Polybius’ contention that justice arose at the origins of
societies when individuals perceived that it was
ultimately in their self-interest to promote norms of
reciprocity by praising those who adhered to them and
blaming those who violated them (D. i.2, p. 107). On
this understanding, human opinion does arguably
become the measure of virtue.
3. Revaluing the Virtues and Vices
Machiavelli may be right that public opinion looks
fondly, and gives the benefit of the moral doubt to,
individuals who have flourished in worldly affairs.
Even so, if we are to take our bearings by opinion as
Machiavelli does, it must also be acknowledged that
people admire qualities that do not necessarily go hand
in hand with the art of acquisition, such as generosity,
humanity, faithfulness, and honesty. Machiavelli well
knows that the commendation of these traits is implicit
in everyday ways of moral speaking. He realizes, too,
that philosophers -- St. Thomas More, for instance --
have envisioned utopias where such traits would
animate the social order. But Machiavelli thinks it
more appropriate to focus on what he calls, “the
effectual truth” (P. xv, p. 61) namely, to what works
in practice, as opposed to what is merely imagined in
theoretical speculation. “And many have imagined
republics and principalities that have never been seen
or known to exist in truth; for it is so far from how one
lives to how one ought to live that he who lets go of
what is done for what should be done learns his ruin
rather than his preservation” (ibid) What
Machiavelli’s statement here connotes is that
businesspersons who orient their conduct around what
ought to be done as all business ethicists prescribe
are essentially opening themselves up to be suckers
and victims of the unprincipled people that abound in
the world. To the extent that the highest praises are
bestowed on founders, and flows downward to
common acquirers, it logically follows for
Machiavelli that no practically relevant teaching on
virtue can recommend a course of action that
ultimately leads to one’s downfall. Consequently,
9
Machiavelli counsels princes to be flexible in their
behaviour, respecting ordinary moral values when
circumstances permit, but transcending them when
interest requires it. This is Machiavellian virtú in a
nutshell. Virtú does not efface traditional virtue, but
preserves it (Mansfield, 1996, pp. 6-52). Still, in its
opposition to time-honored moral understandings,
virtú constitutes an attempt to bring about a
revaluation of values in which acquisitive human
personalities, like those seen in business, will cease to
feel alienated and guilty about taking the measures
needed to assure their success.
Spelling out what this means, Machiavelli first
redefines liberality, the virtue that concerns how a
person deals with money. It is hard to find a time and
a place in which grasping, penny pinchers have been
held in high regard and where generosity has not been
praised. No one, to be sure, is expected to be
extravagant to the point of depleting their own
resources. Nevertheless, it is commonly thought that
each should be ready to give in accord with their
means. Machiavelli, though, appeals to the prospect of
financial ruin to argue for stinginess (P. xvi, pp. 63-
65). Generosity only benefits a leader, he says, if it is
noticed. But as people are not necessarily going to
discern kindness if the bounty is small, generous
leaders must give lavishly in order to secure a good
reputation. Eventually, to finance this, they are forced
to deprive money from some of the people they
oversee in order to shower it on others. A CEO, for
instance, who donates large sums to local charities,
with a view to generating positive media coverage, is
subsequently compelled to reduce departmental
budgets and forgo the customary hike in the stock
dividend, with the result that shareholders and
employees grow to hate the CEO. If, on the other
hand, the CEO is parsimonious, fewer sacrifices will
be required, and, as time passes, he or she will come
to be seen as generous precisely for leaving people
alone. In the Machiavellian recasting, generosity is not
taking.
Machiavelli then shifts his discussion of the virtues
and vices of leaders to the distinction between mercy
and cruelty. Few things, particularly in our times,
shock the conscience more than cruelty; and few
things are more endearing than mercy. Machiavelli, by
contrast, asserts that the value of these depends on the
mode of their employment (P. xvii, pp. 65-68). Mercy
is badly used if it precludes decisive action to remedy
a situation that would otherwise dangerously
intensify. Indeed, for Machiavelli, the more merciful
tack is to carry out the harsh measures necessary to
prevent matters from worsening, since the cruelty will
be felt by few, whereas the cessation of the turmoil
will be enjoyed by many. Mercy is ill used, too, if it
renders one indulgent to the excesses of one’s
officials, as may happen when a CEO looks away as a
member of his or her executive team bullies other
staff. The CEO’s lieutenants are more effectively
utilized, Machiavelli astonishingly suggests, if they
are delegated the dirty work and then dispensed with
once they have served their purpose. In Machiavelli’s
most shocking illustration, he relates the story of
Remirro de Orco, who had been brought in by Cesare
Borgia to restore order and stability in Romagna (P.
vii, pp. 29-30). Sparing no brutality, de Orco quickly
accomplished his assigned task, making a reputation
for himself, though at the price of igniting hatred in
the public. Desiring that this ill-will not carry over to
him, and also that de Orco not outshine him, Borgia
hacked him into two pieces and left his body in a
public square with a bloody knife beside it. “The
ferocity of this spectacle left the people at once
satisfied and stupefied” (P.vii, p. 30).
Timing matters as well, according to Machiavelli.
Cruelty is best done all at once because the pain will
eventually be forgotten (P. vii, pp. 37-38). Stretching
it out in smaller doses, in the hopes that this will create
less heartache, actually fosters hatred because victims
are constantly reminded of who is behind their
suffering. The opposite tack is recommended for acts
of kindness. People granted significant benefits will
only be impressed by something bigger the next time,
whereas a series of smaller gifts delivered over time
can more easily be made to ascend in value to meet
expectations, in addition to continually reinforcing in
the beneficiary’s mind the goodness of the benefactor
(ibid.). What this might entail for business managers
can be readily imagined: give minor, regular raises to
employees and, whenever the economy slows down,
calculate all the labor cost reductions necessary to
make it through the downturn, and announce the
layoffs all at once.
It is mid-way through his analysis of cruelty and
mercy that Machiavelli issues his notorious answer to
the question whether it is better for a leader to be loved
or feared. He indicates that it would be ideal to be
both, but as circumstances usually force one to choose,
the optimal course is to be feared, rather than loved (P.
xvii, pp. 66-67). Love places followers beyond the
leaders’ control, while fear puts obedience in the
hands of the leader. This becomes obvious,
Machiavelli notes, when difficulties arise and
sacrifices are required. Having shown the leader
affection and promised to always stand at their side
when times are good, people will just as quickly
abandon him or her when the times turn rough. “For
one can say this generally of men: that they are
ungrateful, fickle, pretenders and dissemblers, evaders
of danger, eager for gain” (P.xvii, p. 67). Relying on
fear hinders this ugly side of human nature from
hurting the prince because the threat of pain makes it
in people’s interests to obey in every circumstance.
Now an argument could be made, as Cicero did
approximately 1,500 years before, that Machiavelli
underestimates the power of love to bond individuals
to leaders and spur people to rally around them in their
10
hour of need
4
. Cicero (1991) also pointed out that fear
is apt to spark hatred, the breeding ground for revolt
(p. 75). Machiavelli’s counter to this is that it is
possible to avoid hatred while being feared, so long as
one punishes people only with good reason, refrains
from using one’s authority for sexual purposes, and,
most importantly, one avoids seizing people’s
property. In other words, a corporate leader can
successfully rely on fear to maintain their authority if
their forceful acts can be justified, they steer clear of
any behaviour that might be construed as sexual
harassment, and they refrain from denying employees
and shareholders monetary benefits due to them.
Justice -- understood in the ordinary sense as respect
for property and persons in addition to giving each his
due -- is the Machiavellian antidote to the hatred that
fear might instil.
Machiavelli immediately reverts back to the
questioning of ordinary moral notions in analyzing
honesty and fidelity to promises, also commonly
regarded as part of justice. Most people and
philosophers, excepting strict Kantians, have agreed
that the duties of honesty and faithfulness are not to be
adhered to absolutely, but that if a breach is required,
it must be to help others. Hardly anyone thinks that an
individual hiding a Jewish family in their house in
early 1940’s Germany was obliged to tell the truth to
a Nazi official that came knocking at their door asking
whether they know the whereabouts of any Jewish
persons. Machiavelli concurs that the obligation is not
unconditional, though for reasons of the leader’s self-
protection. It would make sense to tell the truth and
keep promises if everyone else did, Machiavelli
admits, but in the competitive universe in which
humans are continually trying to get an edge at others’
expense, that faithfulness cannot be expected. Thus,
Machiavellian leaders must become master
dissemblers and be willing to break promises when it
ceases to be in their interest to adhere to them (P. xviii,
pp. 69-71). One need not be especially clever,
Machiavelli believes, to come up with a plausible
rationalization, which can be rendered all the more
credible if one succeeds and continually sermonizes
about the sanctity of honesty and faith. “Men in
general judge more by their eyes than by their hands
[e]veryone sees how you appear, few touch what
you are” (P.xviii, p. 71). Whatever the merits of this
advice in politics, its value in business may certainly
be suspected, even on Machiavelli’s self-interested
grounds, if only because a liar and promise breaker
will eventually find no one willing to associate and
deal with them. So too, what Machiavelli says is based
on the idea that politicians ultimately play on a stage
before the populace. “For the vulgar are taken in by
the appearance and the outcome of a thing, and in the
world there is no one but the vulgar” (ibid.). But
4
For a more detailed comparison of Machiavelli and Cicero, see
Colish (1978).
businesspersons mostly play a game in which they
interact with other businesspersons, who certainly
have financial incentives to look beyond appearances
before entering a transaction.
Be that as it may, the appearance-reality distinction
that Machiavelli draws is the key to understanding the
contradictory spectacle of putting in a good word for
the traditional virtues and simultaneously invoking
virtú to designate something opposite that is highly
worth emulating. According to Machiavelli, the
traditional virtues properly belong to the realm of
appearance, while virtú is meant to characterize the
reality of a prince who knows how to shift to and from
the old verities and then cover it up effectively without
provoking hatred and opposition. Besides disguising
it with rationalizations, success, and appeals to the
common good, Machiavelli recommends that princes
cultivate an image that is as far from levity,
indecisiveness, spinelessness, and unsteadiness as it is
close to seriousness, resoluteness, courage, and
steadfastness (P, xix, p. 72). They ought to keep a low
profile in their day-to-day administrative tasks so that
the grand enterprises they rarely undertake can shine
all the more brightly. No matter what they do, it should
be done well. Nor should leaders shy away from
seeking fame, which for businesspersons means
getting lionized on the cover of Fortune magazine,
writing articles for The Wall Street Journal, and
publishing books to shares one’s life story,
experiences, and leadership wisdom. Business leaders
can also burnish their image by recognizing the
virtuous (as understood by orthodox standards),
rewarding those who work hard, perform their
functions exceptionally well, and make signal
contributions to the company’s growth. Finally, as a
way to demonstrate concern for the happiness of
employees, Machiavelli urges managers to host
parties during holiday periods, sponsor special events,
and give away prizes in contests (P.xxi, pp. 87-91).
Whether or not all this image management can work
is the big question left hanging from Machiavelli’s
discussion and upon which his entire teaching on
leadership stands or falls. It cannot be illuminated
much by social science studies that attempt to examine
the performance of Machiavellian types versus non-
Machiavellians (Christie and Geis, 1970; Gable and
Topol, 1991; Ricks and Fraedrich, 1999). This
research, in which the connection between
Machiavellianism and business success comes to view
as mixed, identifies a Machiavellian based on how a
person answers a series of questions on the so-called
Mach IV or Mach V scale. No consistent adherent of
Machiavelli would dare admit to others that they are
guided by his teachings. To do so, after all, would be
to raise doubts about one’s trustworthiness, making it
more difficult to obtain the co-operation of others in
11
the advancements of one’s projects. Leaders,
especially, depend on others to follow their direction
and thus can least afford signaling any kind of
opportunism. For this reason, the true Machiavellian
will not disclose their own Machiavellianism. Though
designed by Christie and Geis (1970) to force such
disclosure, responses can be faked (Fehr, Samson,
Paulhus, 1992: 102 citing Skinner, Giokas, &
Hornsstein,1976; Skinner, 1982). A proper empirical
test of Machiavelli’s counsel must imitate his
historical approach in closely scrutinizing the deeds,
statements, and reputations of well-known business
leaders and gauging whether the successful ones were
distinguished by acting in crucial moments with virtú,
while preaching, and being generally presumed to
exemplify, conventional virtue.
Conclusion
While present-day business ethicists differ on a
wide variety of issues, there is a broad consensus that
selfishness ought to be inhibited in the commercial
arena and that business leaders should instead be
consciously driven by a more altruistic set of motives.
We find that Machiavelli fundamentally disagrees
with this consensus -- despite his advocacy of
participatory forms of governance, and the publicly
spirited virtues that go along with it, in the Discourses.
For he concedes that the participatory structure of
republics is ill-suited to organizational contexts that
are in need of radical reform or which must be started
anew. In these cases, Machiavelli insists a princely
leader is necessary. In acknowledging, too, the utility
of temporary dictatorships in republics, he can be
taken to support the temporary dictatorships that the
CEO’s of our day essentially assume in established
and well-functioning companies.
Thus directed to The Prince for business counsel,
we see Machiavelli trying to establish a novel
conception of morality, encapsulated within the notion
of virtú, in which human excellence is equated with
acquisitiveness. This ideal is personified most fully in
the individual who originates new modes and orders,
the founder of a great business. Still, in this
revaluation of values, Machiavelli retains traditional
understandings of virtue that emphasize self-restraint
and altruism. But this is something merely for
business leaders to simulate in normal circumstances.
In more exceptional circumstances, when self-interest
demands it, the moral orthodoxy must be set aside for
the expression of virtú. Machiavellian CEO’s
seemingly devote themselves to the most exalted
principles of business ethics, and leave everyone
convinced that they are doing so, but really operate as
ruthless capitalists.
References
Anonymous. 2003, “Family Businesses Dominate: International
Family Enterprise Research Academy”, Family Business Review, 16
(4), 235-241.
Applegate, J: 1994, “Keep Your Firm in the Family”, Money, 23
(1), 88-91.
Aristotle: 1984, The Complete Works of Aristotle, J. Barnes (ed.)
(Princeton University Press, Princeton).
Beckhard, R & Dyer, W.G: 1983, Managing continuity in the
family owned business”, Organizational Dynamics, 5 (1), 5-12.
Berlin, I: 1972, “The Originality of Machiavelli”, in M.P. Gilmore
(Ed.), Studies on Machiavelli (GC Sansoni, Florence).
Bing, S: 2000, What Would Machiavelli Do: The Ends Justify the
Meanness (Harper Business, New York).
Buono, A.F., Bowditch, D.L., & Lewis, J.W: 1985, “When cultures
collide: The Anatomy of a Merger”, Human Relations, 38 (5), 477-
500.
Christie, R. & Geis, F.L: 1970, Studies in Machiavellianism
(Academic Press, New York).
Cicero: 1991, On Duties, M.T. Griffin and E.M. Atkins (Eds.)
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).
Coase, R: 1937, “The Nature of the Firm”, Economica, 4 (16), 386-
405.
Colish, M.L: 1978, “Cicero’s De Officiis and Machiavelli’s Prince”,
Sixteenth Century Journal, 9 (4), 80-93.
Conway Center for Family Business: 2024, “Family Business
Facts”, Retrievable from,
https://www.familybusinesscenter.com/resources/family-business-
facts/ (accessed November 18, 2024).
Cosans, C., & Reina, C.S.: 2018, “he Leadership Ethics of
Machiavelli’s The Prince”, Business Ethics Quarterly, 28, 275-300.
Di Norcia, V: 1988, Mergers, Takeovers, and a Property Ethic”,
Journal of Business Ethics, 7 (1-2), 109-116.
EY Global: 2023, “How the Largest Family Enterprises Are
Outstripping Global Economic Growth”, Retrievable from,
https://www.ey.com/en_gl/insights/family-enterprise/family-business-
index (accessed November 18, 2024).
Fehr, B., Samson, D., Paulhus, D: 1992, “The Construct of
Machiavellianism: Twenty years later”, in C.D. Spielberger & J.N.
Butcher, (Eds.), Advances in Personality Assessment, Vol. 9.
(Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ).
Finch, N: 2005, “Identifying and Addressing the causes of conflict
in family business”, MGSM Working Paper, Retrievable from,
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=717262, (accessed
January 22, 2009).
Gable, M. & Topol. M.T: 1991, “Machiavellian managers : Do
They Perform Better?” Journal of Business and Psychology, 5 (3), 355-
365.
Galie, P.J. & Bopst, C : 2006, « Machiavelli & Modern Business :
Realist Thought in Contemporary Corporate Manuals”, Journal of
Business Ethics, 65 (3), 235-250.
Goksoy, A.A: 2019, Cultural Integration in Mergers and
Acquisitions” in A.C. Moreira & P. Silva, (Eds.), Handbook of
Research on Corporate Restructuring and Globalization (IGI Global,
Hershey, PA), 101-124.
Griffin, G.R: 1991, Machiavelli on Management : Playing and
Winning the Corporate Power Game. (Praeger, New York).
Harris, P, Lock, A & Rees, P. (Eds): 2000, Machiavelli, Marketing,
and Management, (Routledge, London).
Ledeen, M: 1999, Machiavelli on Leadership : Why Machiavelli’s
Rules are as Timely and Important Today as Five Centuries Ago,
(Truman Talley Books, New York).
Machiavelli, N: 1970, The Discourses, L.J. Walker (trans.) (New
York : Penguin).
_______: 1985, The Prince, H.C. Mansfield (trans.) (University of
Chicago Press, Chicago).
Maity, M., Roy, N., Majumder, D., & Chakravarty, P: 2023,
“Revisiting the Received Image of Machiavelli in Business Ethics
Through a Close Reading of The Prince and Discourses”, Journal of
Business Ethics, 191, 231-252.
Mansfield, H: 1996, Machiavelli’s Virtue, (University of Chicago
Press, Chicago).
McAlpine, A: 1998, The New Machiavelli : The Art of Politics in
Business, (John Wiley, New York).
Miller, D., Steier, L., & Le Breton-Miller, I : 2003, “Lost in Time:
Intergenerational succession, change, and failure in family business”,
Journal of Business Venturing, 18 (4), 513-531.
Morgenson G., & Rosner, J: 2023, These Are the Plunderers: How
Private Equity Runs and Wrecks America, (Simon and Schuster,
New York).
12
Olschiki, L: 1945, Machiavelli the Scientist, (University of
California Press, Berkeley).
Perry, M: 2020. “Only 51 US Companies Have Been on the Fortune
500 Since 1955, Thanks to the Creative Destruction That Fuels
Economic Prosperity”, American Enterprise Institute. Retrievable
from, https://www.aei.org/carpe-diem/only-51-us-companies-have-
been-on-the-fortune-500-since-1955-thanks-to-the-creative-
destruction-that-fuels-economic-prosperity/ (accessed November
18/2024).
Phillips, M: 2018, “GE Dropped From the Dow After More Than a
Century”, New York Times, June 19, 2008. Retrievable from,
https://www.nytimes.com/2018/06/19/business/dealbook/general-
electric-dow-jones.html (accessed November 18, 2024).
Pocock, J.G.A: 1975, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine
Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton
University Press, Princeton).
Plato: 1968, The Republic of Plato, A. Bloom (trans.) (Basic Books,
New York).
Ramsey, M: 2000, “Are Machiavellian tactics still appropriate or
defensible in politics? in P. Harris, A. Lock, & P. Rees (eds.),
Machiavelli, Marketing, and Management, (Routledge, London).
Ricks, J. & Fraedrich, J: 1999, “The Paradox of Machiavellianism:
Machiavellianism May Make for Productive Sales but Poor
Management Reviews”, Journal of Business Ethics, 20 (3), 197-205.
Skinner, N.F., Giokas, J. & Hornstein, H: 1976, “Personality
Correlates of Machiavellianism: 1: Consensual Validation”, Social
Behavior and Personality: An International Journal, 4 (2), 273-276.
Skinner, N.F: 1982, “Personality Correlates of Machiavellianism
III: A Simulation Procedure for identifying high Machs”, Social
Behavior and Personality: An International Journal, 10 (2), 197-199.
Skinner, Q: 2000, Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction. (Oxford
University Press, Oxford).
Smith Family Business Initiative: 2024: “Family Business Facts”,
Cornell SG Johnson College of Business, Retrievable from,
https://business.cornell.edu/centers/smith/resources/family-business-
facts/ (accessed November 18, 2024).
Weber, R. & Comerer, C.F: 2003, “Cultural Conflict and Merger
Failure: An Experimental Approach”, Management Science, 49 (4),
400-415.
Wooldridge, A: 2009 (Mar. 14), “Global Heroes: A Special Report
on Entrepreneurship”, The Economist, 390 (8622), 1-20.